Название: Critique of Rights
Автор: Christoph Menke
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты
isbn: 9781509520428
isbn:
10 10. Cicero, De Officiis, trans. by Walter Miller (London: Heinemann, 1928), 255 (II.78).
11 11. Cicero, De Officiis, 263 (II.85). Nevertheless, this is only one part of justice: it further requires people “to use common possessions for the common interests, private property for their own” (De Officiis, 23 [I.7]).
12 12. Michel Villey, “Suum jus cuique tribuens,” in: Studi in onore di Pietro de Francisci (Milan: Antonino Giuffre, 1956), vol. 1, 363–71, here 365.
13 13. Michel Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne, ed. by Stéphane Rials (Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 2006), 247.
14 14. Cicero, De Officiis, 211 (II.41–2).
15 15. Michel Villey, Le droit roman (Paris: PUF, 1964), 20.
16 16. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. by A.V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 290.
17 17. Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne, 247.
18 18. Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne, 249.
19 19. Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne, 247. Roman law “refrained from providing a definition of the content of the right of ownership” (Villey, Le droit roman, 84).
20 20. For the relation of private law and the commencement of action, see chapter 10, “Claiming One’s Own,” in this volume.
21 21. Body of Civil Law, in: The Institutes of Justinian, trans. by Thomas Collett Sandar (London: Longmans, Green, 1878), 13–17 [I.3.1].]
22 22. Michel Villey, “La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d’Occam,” Archives de philosophie du droit, IX (1964), 97–127, here 104.
23 23. Cf. the critique of Villey in Richard Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 22–4, and Brian Tierney, The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law, and Church Law 1150–1625 (Grand Rapids/Cambridge: Eerdmans, 2001), 13–42. Both criticize Villey’s fixation on Ockham, and not merely on the grounds of historical fidelity. They also criticize his fixation by arguing that the idea of natural rights (in Ockham, and, for Villey, beyond) is rooted in philosophical nominalism. For this, see also the discussion of the relation between the logical and the legal-political category of the individual [Individuums] in Ockham by Arthur Stephen McGrade, “Ockham and the Birth of Individual Rights,” in: Brian Tierney and Peter Linehan (eds.), Authority and Power: Studies on Medieval Law and Government Presented to Walter Ullmann on his Seventieth Birthday (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), 149–65 esp. 149–51. Lastly, for an overview of the debate and a defense of Villey – both his interpretation of Ockham and the critique of modernity that he based upon it – see John Milbank, “Against Human Rights: Liberty in the Western Tradition,” Oxford Journal of Law and Religion, 1 (2012), 1–32. Villey’s insight into the fundamental difference between the modern and traditional – Greek and Roman – idea of rights is not affected by the question of his interpretation of Ockham.
24 24. Villey, “La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d’Occam,” 112.
25 25. Villey, “La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d’Occam,” 114f.
26 26. William of Ockham, A Letter to the Friars Minor and Other Writings, trans. by John Kilcullen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 21.
27 27. Villey, “La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d’Occam,” 117.
28 28. Ockham, Letter to the Friars Minor, 24. See also, in this volume, p. 9.
29 29. Giorgio Agamben, The Highest Poverty: Monastic Rules and Form-of-Life (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011), 115. Agamben cites Villey (134), but misinterprets him as having overlooked Ockham’s subtlety and attributes to him the intention of developing an affirmative concept of “subjective right.” Villey’s thesis, however, is precisely that Ockham unintentionally created this concept, and thus that his subtlety got him into trouble. One can speak of a systematic suppression of the modern character of rights in Agamben. For this, see chapter 6, “Excursus: The Biopolitical Context (Agamben),” in this volume.
30 30. Agamben, Highest Poverty, 138.
31 31. Agamben, Highest Poverty, 113.
32 32. Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 194. This initially holds true for the right (as power) of the sovereign: “only if potentia and potestas essentially belong together, can there be a guaranty of the actualization of the right social order” (194). Yet it defines the concept of legal power in general, regardless of whether it is the power of the sovereign or of an individual.
33 33. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan or The Matter, Forme, & Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiasticall and Civil, ed. by Richard Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 200.
34 34. Hobbes, Leviathan, 91.
35 35. Benedict de Spinoza, A Theological-Political Treatise, trans. by Michael Silverthorne and Jonathan Israel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 195.
36 36. Spinoza, Theological-Political Treatise, 195–6.
37 37. Hobbes, Leviathan, 117. For the “final cause” or “end” of the state see Hobbes’ discussion over the next few sections following this citation in Leviathan, passim. At a similar point, Spinoza speaks of “interest” in Theological-Political Treatise, 224. Leo Strauss (The Political Philosophy of Hobbes [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952], 43) and Carl Schmitt (The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes, trans. by George Schwab and Erna Hilfstein [Westport: Greenwood, 1996], 91, 96) refer to this goal-oriented character of the state, its advantageous character, when they call the concept of the state in the natural law tradition a “technical” concept.
38 38. [Tr. – Hobbes’ conception of “the sovereign” does not require that it СКАЧАТЬ