Critique of Rights. Christoph Menke
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Critique of Rights - Christoph Menke страница 17

Название: Critique of Rights

Автор: Christoph Menke

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509520428

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ id="uc046b8db-f004-5383-be51-a0cc66bde2d6">

      To understand different legal systems, we should first ask: how is law apportioned or distributed? To put this more precisely: what does it mean to say that law safeguards the respectively obligation-imposing claims of individuals? And how does law understand the nature of these claims? How does such safeguarding define the equality of law [Recht]? And how does this determine the concept of law [Gesetz]?

       1 Athens

      Greek legal theory grasps the concept of a right – as Aristotle puts it in the fifth book of the Nicomachean Ethics – in its definition of “corrective” justice, “corresponding to the two classes of private transactions, those which are voluntary and those which are involuntary.”1 It is essential that transactions regulated by corrective justice involve a relationship between equals. Such justice does not involve the relationship to an “officer.”2 Corrective justice constitutes the field of private law and applies to both voluntary and involuntary transactions. In other words, it applies to “the interchange of services … in the form of Reciprocity,” in which the parties concerned exchange goods with one another. And it also applies to transactions in which one party has injured another, and where the resulting damage must now be corrected.

      Thus the just is a sort of mean, inasmuch as the judge is a medium between the litigants. Now the judge restores equality: if we represent the matter by a line divided into two unequal parts, he takes away from the greater segment that portion by which it exceeds one-half of the whole line, and adds to it the lesser segment. When the whole has been divided into two halves, people then say that each “has their share,” having got what is equal.4

      Aristotle’s conception of one person’s right vis-à-vis another is that a person has the right to his own. In the case of loss, a judge corrects this right by awarding restitution to the aggrieved party, so that the latter thereby recoups his just or equal share:

      to have more than one’s own is called gaining, and to have less than one had at the outset is called losing, as for instance in buying and selling, and all other transactions sanctioned by law; while if the result of the transaction is neither an increase nor a decrease, but exactly what the parties had of themselves, they say they “have their own” and have neither lost nor gained. Hence Justice in involuntary transactions is a mean between gain and loss in a sense: it is to have after the transaction an amount equal to the amount one had before it.5

      The right that one party has is his own as equal share. The individual’s claim is the just share, which is due him according to the rules of equal distribution.

      This is just as applicable to the voluntary transaction between persons in exchange, in which justice does not exclusively require providing restitution for a loss, but can also be satisfied by simply engaging in a quid pro quo with the other party. To be sure, equality cannot be understood here in arithmetical terms (as is the case in restitution, where the loss suffered is rectified: “For it makes no difference whether a good man has defrauded a bad man or a bad man a good one”).6 Proportional justice, however, which determines the exchange of different goods, has precisely the same meaning: it produces a state of equality – a state in which it can be said that, with his just share, each has received his own.

      The demands that individuals make on each other are legal claims, which they are entitled to make against one another, if the goal is for each to “have their own.” Similarly, in contract and indemnity law, both exchange and restitution require a state of equality that defines individuals’ respective entitlements. “Thus attention to the equality of gain and loss in corrective justice [C.M. – likewise with the equality of rendering a service and receiving the same in return in contract law] presupposes the notional equality of initial holdings,”8 which is either compensated for in restitution or realized in exchange. Equitable distribution determines what this equality of shares or “initial holdings” (as Weinrib puts it) consists in, however, and thereby determines each person’s own: right as one’s own is what is commensurate or corresponds to each person as he is. Just as the arithmetical equality of rectification presupposes that distribution disrupted by loss was rectified,9 so the proportional equality of exchange consists in the realization of goods and rendering of services according to their relative significance in the life of the community – in the satisfaction of needs whose regulation is the state’s political responsibility. The fair share is the basis for corrective equality and for the equality of exchange. Right [Recht] as an individual’s claim is based on law [Recht] as just order. The proper ordering of persons and objects whose regulation, production, and safeguarding is a political matter, and forms the basis for any private claim that one individual is entitled to make vis-à-vis another.

       2 Rome

      Roman law adopts, virtually unchanged, the basic definition of the legal claim, which was framed by a moral understanding of law in Athens. In Rome, the fact that someone has a right, and thus a justified claim on someone else, also means that such a claim is his own, that it rightfully belongs to him, and that, in particular, it is his fair share of something. Justice – in other words, a state of affairs in which persons and things stand in a relation of equality – is the basis of rights. Cicero is drawing on this when he reproaches “the friends of the people,” who push for a redistribution of land and the eviction of previous owners:

      Anyone deprived of his own suffers an injustice. In contrast, those who make it their business “to look after the interest of the state” see to it that “every one shall be protected in the possession of his own property by the fair administration of the law and courts.”11 Laws founded on right [Rechtsgesetze] articulate what constitutes relations of justice or equality, and what is appropriate for each person in such just relations is his own. This is his right: the right that a person has is his own, and justly belongs to him. “To each his own: suum tribuens…. It is the task of justice to apply to each and every thing the legal provision that corresponds to it.”12 Equitable distribution precedes an individual’s right, and is the subject matter of legal practice. “Ius is the share that is awarded СКАЧАТЬ