Market Theory and the Price System. Israel M. Kirzner
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Market Theory and the Price System - Israel M. Kirzner страница 22

Название: Market Theory and the Price System

Автор: Israel M. Kirzner

Издательство: Ingram

Жанр: Экономика

Серия: The Collected Works of Israel M. Kirzner

isbn: 9781614872528

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ stock of a good as, at the same time, increasing his store of utility afforded by possession of the good. The total store of utility afforded by the entire stock would be the sum of the successive increments of utility obtained as the stock successively expanded from the acquisition of the first unit up to the addition of the last acquired unit. The rate at which the addition of successive physical units of the good increases the total utility of a stock of the good is termed (in the cardinal terminology) the “marginal utility” of the good.3

      The ideas, however, underlying the cardinal approach present considerable conceptual difficulty. Without attempting to enlarge on this difficulty, we can contrast this approach with the currently more accepted ordinal approach. This view denies the very notion of cardinal quantities of utility. The only numbers that can be assigned to utilities are ordinal numbers. Utilities can be arranged in order; for example, first, second, and so on. They cannot however be assigned numerical magnitude. A shirt may be said to have greater utility than an apple; one may not say how many times the utility of the shirt is greater. A “unit” of utility has no meaning for the ordinal approach. When men value goods, they arrange them in order of value; they do not attach cardinal numbers to them.

      The discussion we have presented in this chapter follows the ordinal approach to utility. For us, the utility of a good corresponds to a ranking on the scale of values; to speak of the utility of a good is to involve only the comparison of its significance with that of some other good. An important consequence of our adopting this ordinal viewpoint is that the term “marginal utility” is used in this book in a somewhat different sense from its use in a “cardinal” approach. This matter of terminology needs a brief explanation.

       Total Utility and Marginal Utility

      For a cardinal utility theorist, we have seen, the term “marginal utility” is used in contradistinction to “total utility.” Total utility refers to the quantity of (cardinal) utility afforded by a stock of a commodity. Marginal utility refers to the rate at which total utility changes as the size of the stock of the commodity changes. An approximation to this rate of change of total utility is given by the amount of change in that utility resulting from a one-unit increase in the stock of the commodity. (Sometimes cardinal utility theorists loosely refer to this approximation as “marginal utility.”)4

      For ordinal utility theory, such a distinction between total and marginal utility is not called for. Since there is no cardinal quantity of utility that increases, there can be no such concept as a rate of change of such a quantity. For an ordinal theory, marginal utility means the significance attached to the addition to (or decrease of) the quantity possessed of a good by the marginal unit. It does not, it must be noticed, refer to a change in the significance of the stock of the good, but to the significance of a change in the size of the stock. But total utility, too, for the ordinal theorist means the significance attached to the acquisition or loss of a given stock of the commodity. Both the utility of a stock of a good and the marginal utility of a marginal unit being added (or subtracted) from the stock “are total utilities” (in that they do not refer to “rates of change”); but, and more important, at the same time they are both “marginal utilities” in the sense that the utility of any quantity of a good, large or small, implies that this quantity is being considered “marginally”—that is, that somebody is contemplating the acquisition or loss of this quantity.

      The “marginal unit,” in fact, is never anything else than the unit that happens to be under consideration. It is the unit relevant to the act of choice confronting a man. The size of this unit depends only on the circumstances of the situation where a choice has become necessary. A man may be contemplating the purchase of several shirts. For certain sums of money, he can buy one, two, or several shirts. In choosing among the alternatives open to him, the man will be comparing the marginal utilities of the appropriate number of shirts—that is, the smallest number of shirts separating one possible decision from another. If any number of shirts can be bought, then a single shirt is the marginal unit; if shirts can be bought only in packages of three, then three shirts make up the marginal unit—and the decision whether or not to buy additional shirts will involve the difference that three more shirts will make to the purchaser’s sense of well-being. Suppose a situation where a man is forced to choose between purchasing all of a supply of shirts or of obtaining none at all; then the entire supply would be the relevant “unit.” The man must assess the difference that the entire supply would mean to him in considering the attractiveness of the price it can be had at. In such a situation the marginal unit is the entire supply, and the man is in a position where the “marginal utility of shirts” means nothing else than the significance to him of this entire shirt supply.

       MARGINAL UTILITY AND THE CONDITIONS FOR EXCHANGE

      The utility analysis discussed in this chapter provides a framework within which to understand the emergence of exchange between individuals. Interpersonal exchange is the essence of the market process, and market theory is devoted to the explanation of the way objects will be produced for exchange, the quantities that will be offered for exchange, and the rates at which different exchanges will take place. Here we analyze the basic conditions that exist when two individuals exchange goods. This analysis will be fundamental to much of the subsequent material in this book.

      The conditions for exchange exist between two individuals A, B, whenever a specific quantity of a good possessed by A is ranked lower on his value scale than a specific quantity of a good possessed by B, while the ordering is the reverse on B’s value scale. That is, wherever the marginal utility of a quantity of one good possessed by A is lower for A than that of a quantity of another good possessed by B, while for B the marginal utility of the latter quantity is the lower, then each of the two gain by giving up what is less important to him in exchange for what is more important.

      If these conditions are absent, no exchange can take place. It is not sufficient that A ranks B’s brand new automobile higher than his own ancient jalopy; if B concurs in A’s relative valuation, both vehicles will remain where they are. No exchange will take place freely unless each party believes that he will be better off having made the exchange. This fundamental and self-evident truth is the central theme of the market process and of its theory.

      The implications of these conclusions are far reaching. Where two men each possess both of two goods, then, as we have seen, any difference in the rankings that specific quantities of the two goods occupy on the value scales of the two men will result in exchange if the two men are “in the same market” (that is, if they are each in contact with the other and aware of the other’s relative ranking). This is so because it will benefit each man to give some of the good he values less for some of the good he values more. A state of rest, where both men, although in the same market, do not barter, can exist therefore only when both men rank both goods in the same order on their individual scales of value. But if this is so for two goods, it is so for any two goods. Thus, for two men to be in a state of rest with respect to each other, each must rank the marginal quantities of all the goods, which both possess, in exactly the same order as does the other.

      Moreover, if this is the condition for absence of exchange between two men, it must be so also for any two men. Thus, for a market to be at rest, each participant in a market must rank each one of the goods he possesses in exactly the same order of significance, at the margin, as does every other participant in the market.

      To put the same proposition in a different and more useful form, in any market a tendency will exist for each participant to barter in the marketplace so long as the relative marginal utilities to him of all the goods he possesses is in anyway different from those of any other СКАЧАТЬ