Political Theory. Pete Woodcock
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Political Theory - Pete Woodcock страница 12

Название: Political Theory

Автор: Pete Woodcock

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509531363

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ equal to the scenario when the child was rescued for purer motives. For Bentham, those things that promote happiness are good, and those that lead to pain are bad; this applies just as much to politics and government legislation as it does to ethics.

      Jeremy Bentham is generally regarded as the founding father of utilitarianism. Bentham was born in 1748 in London, and educated at Oxford. In addition to his writing on utilitarianism, he was a leading social reformer of his day. Whereas he was an opponent of natural rights arguments, he nevertheless supported the notion of legal rights when they could be said to increase the overall happiness of the people.

      You can still visit Bentham to this day. Bentham played a role in founding University College London, and left his body to the college. His mummified remains are displayed in the main reception area.

      Other utilitarians include father and son team James and John Stuart Mill and Henry Sidgwick. It still has proponents in the contemporary world, with the works of Australian philosopher Peter Singer, who uses the idea to support vegetarianism and giving all of our disposable income to charity.

      Utilitarian philosophers critiqued a large array of social and political policies when they were writing. For example, they championed reforms of the punishments that prisoners received; not upon the grounds of morality or rights, per se, but more on the overall manner in which they worked and the results that they brought about. One such reform was that of lowering the punishments associated with crimes such as theft. Utilitarians in Britain in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century noticed a problem with sentencing. Offences that we would regard as minor today such as theft might still be punishable by death. So the problem was that if you are caught stealing a pig, you have absolutely no incentive to go quietly and accept your punishment; if the punishment for stealing a pig is the same as killing the person who caught you stealing the pig, then you might as well fight your way out of the situation. You would have little to lose at this point, and the overall happiness would be improved by more lenient penal laws. Again, these proposals were put forward not because of human rights concerns, but to produce more happiness.

      Governments take actions that lead to some people suffering all the time. Winston Churchill left Coventry undefended from Luftwaffe raids in the Second World War despite knowing that it was going to be attacked. He got the information from the captured Enigma machines, whose code had been deciphered by Alan Turing and his team at Bletchley Park, and feared that if he defended Coventry too rigorously, the Germans would suspect that their code had been broken, change it, and all strategic advantage would be lost. This would prolong the war, and possibly result in greater loss of life. Likewise, Truman had to consider this when the option of using the atomic bomb was available to him. American troops were in the process of island hopping on the Japanese archipelago at the time, and the hope was the dreadful firepower of atomic bombs would bring the war to a swifter conclusion and consequently save lives despite the terrible casualties. The residents of Coventry and Hiroshima at the time may dispute this philosophical sleight of hand.

      These are extreme examples. When a government decides to give a shipbuilding contract to a port here, rather than there, its actions will negatively affect some citizens for the greater good. Similarly, if a person’s family home is demolished to make way for a motorway, wind turbines spoil the view from your study library, roadworks cause your commute to be extended by 20 minutes every day for the summer, and so on. Sometimes politics involves trade-offs between people’s interests. Whereas utilitarians don’t think people have rights, they do think they have interests, and these interests need to be borne in mind when discussing politics and ethics.

      Activity 3. Please attempt the following tasks:

      1 Why does Bentham think that rights are nonsense on stilts?

      2 What is meant by rule utilitarianism?

      3 Do you think that the person rescuing the child in the pond due to the attractive celebrity close by was committing a moral act?

      Immanuel Kant has no time for utilitarianism, or consequentialism of any flavour for that matter. For him, politics must always ‘bend the knee’ to morality, that is to say that morality is more important than politics and we should do what is right even if this makes us less happy than if we did not.

       Kant

      Immanuel СКАЧАТЬ