Philosophy of Existence. Karl Jaspers
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Philosophy of Existence - Karl Jaspers страница 5

Название: Philosophy of Existence

Автор: Karl Jaspers

Издательство: Ingram

Жанр: Философия

Серия:

isbn: 9780812200867

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ any final rest and peace.

      In one sense, of course, there is no union with being, pure and simple. Jaspers is not a mystic. Access to being can be had only through the world. Only as one participates in the levels of existence, consciousness in general and spirit in an attitude of reason, can one interpret his historical situation and his daily task as appearances of being, his acts of knowing as revelations of being, and his spiritual creations as its symbols. All these things become ciphers of ultimate reality which must be interpreted by each Existenz. Although nothing is a cipher by any natural right or special property, everything can be seen as a cipher pointing to being itself. Philosophizing is the process of allowing all things to open themselves to being and become its symbols.

      Reality can be grasped only historically in terms of particular symbols. Hence there can be no adequate interpretation of it. Unlike religion, which makes transcendence into a supernatural determinate object, philosophizing brings all things into the domain of reason and regards them as transparent ciphers pointing to being. Because in philosophizing each individual recognizes his own truth as a mere cipher, he is able to recognize and respect the truths of other Existenzen and historical traditions. They are ciphers, also. Everything is united in the One. When this state of mind is reached, an attitude emerges which Jaspers in another place calls absolute consciousness. Here, in the vision which perceives being in all finite things, the quest finds an ultimate rest. One senses that being is and stands silent before the ultimate mystery.

      With the mention of reason and reality and the contrast with religion and its objectifying view, we are back at our starting point. Now perhaps we can see what Jaspers means by calling philosophy a process of philosophizing, an inner action whose result is not knowledge of any object, or a theory about objects, but a vision of authentic reality in its symbolic appearances. This vision is at the same time an awareness of one's own authentic being. This attitude of mind and thought which transcends everything finite and objective, allowing being itself to reveal itself in its appearances, is what Jaspers means by the perennial philosophy. It has taken many forms, but today, because of the objectifying tendency in modern thought and culture, this philosophy must become an existential philosophy.

      RICHARD F. GRABAU

      * Philosophy, 3 vols; E. B. Ashton, trans., University of Chicago Press, 1969-1971.

      

Philosophy of Existence

      I HAVE been invited to speak about the philosophy of existence.1 Part of philosophy today goes by this name. The distinguishing term “existence” is meant to emphasize that it is of the present.

      What is called philosophy of existence is really only a form of the one, primordial philosophy. It is no accident, however, that for the moment the word “existence” became the distinguishing term. It emphasized the task of philosophy that for a time had been almost forgotten: to catch sight of reality at its origin and to grasp it through the way in which I, in thought, deal with myselfin inner action. From mere knowledge of something, from ways of speaking, from conventions and role-playing—from all kinds of foreground phenomena—philosophizing wanted to find its way back to reality. Existenz is one of the words for reality, with the accent Kierkegaard gave it: everything essentially real is for me only by virtue of the fact that I am I myself. We do not merely exist; rather, our existence is entrusted to us as the arena and the body for the realization of our origin.

      Already in the nineteenth century, movements with this turn of mind kept recurring. People wanted “life,” wanted “really to live.” They demanded “realism.” Instead of wanting merely to know, they wanted to experience for themselves. Everywhere, they wanted the “genuine,” searched for “origins,” and wanted to press on to man himself. Superior men became more clearly visible; at the same time, it became possible to discover the true and the real in the smallest particle.

      If for a century now the tenor of the age has been entirely different—namely, one of leveling, mechanization, the development of a mass mentality and universal interchangeability of everything and everyone where no one seemed to exist any longer as himself, it was also a stimulating background. Men who could be themselves woke up in this pitiless atmosphere in which every individual was sacrificed as individual. They wanted to take themselves seriously; they searched for the hidden reality; they wanted to know what was knowable; and they thought that by understanding themselves they could arrive at the foundation of their being.

      But even this thinking frequently degenerated into the frivolous veiling of reality that is characteristic of the leveling process, by perversion into a tumultuous and pathetic philosophy of feeling and life. The will to experience being for oneself could be perverted into a contentment with the merely vital; the will to find the origin into a mania for primitivism; the sense of rank into a betrayal of the genuine orders of value.

      We do not propose to consider in its totality this loss of reality in an age of apparently heightened realism—an age out of whose growing awareness developed the soul's distress, and philosophizing. Instead, we shall attempt to recall by an historical account the tortuous route taken by this return to reality—a return that took many shapes—using as an example our relation to the sciences, an example that is inherently essential to our theme.

      AT THE TURN of the century, philosophy was for the most part conceived as one science among others. It was a field of academic study, and was approached by young people as an educational possibility. Sparkling lectures offered vast surveys of its history, its doctrines, problems and systems. Vague feelings of a freedom and truth often devoid of content (because rarely effective in actual life) combined with a faith in the progress of philosophical knowledge. The thinker “advanced further” and was convinced that with each step he stood at the summit of knowledge attained up to that time.

      This philosophy, however, seemed to lack self-confidence. The boundless respect of the age for the exact empirical sciences made them the great exemplar. Philosophy wanted to regain its lost reputation before the judgment seat of the sciences by means of equal exactness. To be sure, all objects of inquiry had been parcelled out to the special sciences. But philosophy wanted to legitimize itself alongside of them by making the whole into a scientific object; the whole of knowledge, for example, by means of epistemology (since the fact of science in general was after all not the object of any particular science); the whole of the universe by means of a metaphysics constructed by analogy with scientific theories, and with their aid; the totality of human ideals by means of a doctrine of universally valid values. These seemed to be objects that did not belong to any special science and yet ought to be open to investigation by scientific methods. Nevertheless, the basic tenor of all this thinking was ambiguous. For it was at once scientific-objective and moral-normative. Men could think they were establishing a harmonious union between the “needs of the mind” and the “results of the sciences.” Finally, they could say that they merely wanted objectively to understand the possible world-views and values, and yet again could claim at the same time to be giving the one true world-view: the scientific.

      Young people in those days were bound to experience a deep disillusionment. This was not what they had thought philosophy was all about. The passion for a life-grounding philosophy made them reject this scientific philosophy which was impressive in its methodological rigor and its demands for arduous thought, and thus at least of educational value, but was basically too innocuous, too easily satisfied, too blind to reality. Demanding reality, they rejected empty abstractions that, for all their systematic orderliness yet seemed like children's games; they rejected proofs that proved nothing despite great ostentation. There were some who took the hint implicit in the hidden self-condemnation of this philosophy which took its own measure from the empirical sciences; they pursued the empirical sciences themselves; they abandoned СКАЧАТЬ