The Metaphysics of German Idealism. Martin Heidegger
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Metaphysics of German Idealism - Martin Heidegger страница 7

Название: The Metaphysics of German Idealism

Автор: Martin Heidegger

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509540129

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ mysterious experiences in play, which destine us to persevere with thought and to awaken a thinking which questions? This can suffice least of all in the realm of thought; here, cold audacity alone has the word. But this, too, is again only an assertion, which, moreover, takes it to be already decided that we are actually placed into a necessity to think. We appear thus again, only in another direction, to rush ahead endlessly on the path of misgivings. And is it not by now already clear that misgivings {Bedenken} most of all hinder us from thinking {Denken}?

      Then, as a point of fact, everything hinges precisely on “making” a beginning in thought without having any misgivings. But should we then still engage with “the historiographic” at all? If not, where should we begin? How insignificant the aforementioned misgivings – regarding the restriction to a particular text of a single thinker – now seem in relation to the objection that, in reflecting on the metaphysics of German Idealism, we are already running after something past and “orienting” ourselves “historiographically.” This sort of orientation contains, after all, the admission that philosophy would only be the historiographical making-present of its past, which it admittedly must be when it no longer finds “a measure or rule” in itself. Schelling expressed himself clearly enough on this matter in the final paragraph of his Freedom Treatise (415):2

      If the dialectical principle, that is, the understanding which is differentiating but thereby organically ordering and shaping things in conjunction with the archetype by which it steers itself, is withdrawn from philosophy so that philosophy no longer has in itself either measure or rule, then nothing else is left to philosophy but to seek to orient itself historiographically and to take the tradition as its source and plumb line […]. Then it is time, as one intended to ground our poetry through acquaintance with the literature of all nations, to seek for philosophy a historical norm and foundation as well.

      4

      But Schelling turns against this time and says:

      The time of merely historiographical faith is past, if the possibility of immediate cognition is given. We have an older revelation than any written one – nature. (Ibid.)

      5

      If, however, as our undertaking suggests, we do not abandon the historical reflection on the metaphysics of German Idealism – but perhaps first introduce it, in fact, and thereby nevertheless act only from the one necessity {Notwendigkeit} to think in the sense of essential thinking – then that is a sign that our necessities are different, different because the need {Not} has become a different one. Or is it perhaps even the same need, not the need of an age, not the need of a century, but the need of two millennia, the need arising from the fact that, ever since then, thinking has been “metaphysics”? Perhaps this need has meanwhile become more pressing, which does not preclude that it has become even less visible. Indeed, our thinking, when it attempts to reflect on German Idealism historically, is not a historiographic orientation; but neither is it “immediate cognition” in the manner of the metaphysics of German Idealism. The thinking that has become necessary is a historical thinking. An actual attempt should clarify what this means.

      We will therefore now leave all misgivings about our undertaking to the side; we will, however, attend to how they resolve and sort themselves out in due course. For a long time to come, we will perhaps not be able to distinguish historiographic explanation from historical thinking. Yet this we shall keep in mind, namely, that the historical thinking attempted here can be subsumed neither under philosophicalhistoriographic explanation nor under “systematic” reflection, nor under a mixture of both. It suffices if we glean from what has been said, even if only in broad strokes, the manner in which we do not arbitrarily and blindly take up Schelling’s treatise so as to publicize it for erudite ends.

      6

      Schelling’s treatise bears the title: “Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom and the Matters Connected Therewith.” It appeared in the year 1809 as the final part of a collection of investigations that Schelling had already published earlier and that were selected from the totality of his existing publications in order to serve as an introduction to the “Freedom Treatise.”

      Cite the four preceding parts (do not at first go into the “works” and biography):

      1 Of the I as Principle of Philosophy, or, On the Unconditional in Human Knowledge (1795)

      2 Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism (1795)

      3 Treatises on the Elucidation of the Idealism of the Doctrine of Science (1796–1797)

      4 On the Relation of the Fine Arts to Nature: An Academic Speech (1807)

      The text of the Freedom Treatise will be cited according to volume and page numbers of the edition of Schelling’s Sämtliche Werke, 1856–1861, fourteen volumes.3 The Freedom Treatise can be found in volume VII, pp. 336–416. These page numbers are printed on the inner margin of the edition of the Philosophische Bibliothek.4

      7

      Depending on how human freedom in its essence belongs to this nexus or even determines it, the treatise on human freedom either is an isolated and separate reflection or comprises the “innermost centerpoint of philosophy …” (Preface 1809, p. VIII).

      The treatise goes into the center of the system as the “system of freedom.

      In СКАЧАТЬ