Free Speech. Jonathan Seglow
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Free Speech - Jonathan Seglow страница 7

Название: Free Speech

Автор: Jonathan Seglow

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509526482

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ that are less appealing, so cogent and well-founded views will tend to win out over weaker ones in the realm of competing ideas.

      But what is really important for Mill is the process of discovery of more well-founded views. As independent-minded individuals employing our reasoning capacities together, we discuss and deliberate about what is most significant, persuasive, justifiable and so on in various fields. This is what serves our happiness as progressive beings – a happiness of a higher kind. In principle one could imagine an omniscient dictatorship, which used censorship and indoctrination to ensure that citizens hold only true or valid opinions and did so even as it curtailed free speech (Ten 1980). But such a ‘dictatorship of truth’ would possess no value for Mill, because in his eyes utility ultimately resides in people’s opportunity to employ their deliberative capacities. Robbed of this opportunity, citizens would not enjoy the practice of gradually arriving at more defensible views (cf. Brink 2008).

      Three specific arguments for free speech, all based on the discovery of truth, can be found in the pages of Mill’s long defence in On Liberty. First, he argues, free speech should be protected because otherwise some cogent or well-founded views would be silenced. As no one knows for sure which views those are, people who restrict the speech of others because they wrongly assume their own infallibility risk depriving themselves and others of the knowledge of silenced yet true opinions. This is often referred to as the infallibility argument. Among the many examples with which Mill illustrates it, that of Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) stands out as especially powerful. An early defender of heliocentrism, Galilei was forced by the Catholic Church to recant his views, which were considered heretical. This act of censorship, grounded in the Church’s assumption that it infallibly ‘knew’ that the sun revolves around the earth, delayed people’s appreciation of the scientific truth. More importantly, it deprived them of the utility that results from genuine knowledge of the universe and from the evaluation of that knowledge through their critical powers. Without free speech, the truth may take longer to emerge – if not fail to do so altogether.

      Third, Mill argues that the most defensible position on many subjects is frequently not captured by any single view but is instead shared among different ones. Each view is therefore partially correct, and hence it is important to allow as many opinions as possible to circulate in order for the full truth to emerge (Mill 2006, p. 55). Political parties, he argues, are among the clearest real-world manifestations of this process. More generally, the partial truth argument seems to be especially suitable for explaining the importance of free speech when it comes to moral and political issues, where disagreement is generally the norm, as opposed for example to scientific matters, where the truth often is, indeed, all on one side.

      While Mill does not emphasise, in On Liberty, the ways in which speech can harm, he does not overlook them either. In a famous passage, he writes:

      An opinion that corn-dealers are starvers of the poor, or that private property is robbery, ought to be unmolested when simply circulated through the press, but may justly incur punishment when delivered orally to an excited mob assembled before the house of a corn-dealer, or when handed about among the same mob in the form of a placard. (Mill 2006, p. 64)

      Other restrictions consistent with Mill’s doctrine concern forms of free speech that invade a person’s self-regarding liberty to determine her own life (within the bounds of the harm principle). According to a Mill scholar such as Jonathan Riley (2005), examples in this category include the malicious invasion of another person’s privacy, libellous speech that damages a person’s social reputation, and false advertising in which manufacturers exploit consumers’ relative ignorance about their products. Exactly what justifies these restrictions raises difficult issues in Mill scholarship, but the general answer is that these types of speech not only harm others; they also contribute little or nothing to the process of discovering truths that people have an interest in knowing (cf. Brink 2008).

      Thus, in a landmark US Supreme Court case in the early 1940s, a Jehovah’s witness was accused of using ‘fighting words’ – that is, words that provoke an immediate and often violent reaction in the listener – against a police officer. The Court ruled that ‘such utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and morality’ (Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 1942). It is worth noting that in all such cases the harm is relatively short term and directed at specific individuals, and thus easy to assess within Mill’s consequentialist framework. Where harms are longer term and more diffuse, they raise, among other issues, questions about the responsibility of the speaker (Ten 1980), as we shall see in later chapters, when we discuss hate speech and pornography.

      A further issue is that Mill seems to rely on an overly optimistic view of the likely consequences of free speech. Permissive public debate may result not in human progress, as measured by the discovery of truth and the development of our deliberative capacities, but in the rise and spread of extremist and other harmful views, with potentially catastrophic consequences for liberal democracy. Nazi Germany, for example, emerged from the thoroughly liberal Weimar Republic, and there are many recent examples of populism and far-right extremism in Europe, the United States, India and elsewhere, all spreading through a culture of free speech. Populist movements are often marked by the phenomenon of groupthink and a culture of intolerance; they do not consist of citizens who dispassionately think through the issues for themselves (and the same may be true to some extent of liberal regimes, too). Of course, whether speech should be limited in order to protect СКАЧАТЬ