Название: Amphion Orator
Автор: Michael Taormina
Издательство: Bookwire
Жанр: Документальная литература
Серия: Biblio 17
isbn: 9783823302490
isbn:
While the notion of virtuevirtue exercised considerable influence on noble identitynobilityidentity in the early decades of the seventeenth century, there existed ideological confusion about which virtuevirtue was most important. The contest was essentially between magnanimitymagnanimity and moderationvirtuemoderation, and this choice reflected the contest between the older warrior ethosethos and the newer worldly ethosethos. Scholars have traced both virtuevirtues to the reception of the Nicomachean EthicsAristotleNicomachean Ethics (NE) in seventeenth-century France.2 Prior to Farethonnête hommeFaret, Nicolas’s treatise, a military hero could be described as honnêtehonnête hommehonnêteté [honorable, noble] and could even be an honnêtehonnête homme homme [honorable man]. But the term would be increasingly reserved for performances within a specific context. It was understood that the battlefield or military camp required different virtuevirtues than the courtroyal court or the aristocratic salonsalons. Magnanimitymagnanimity leads one to perform heroic exploits, whereas moderationvirtuemoderation is a virtuevirtue that describes the right attitude toward pleasure, implying not just self-control but, and above all, enjoyment of to kalon (AristotleAristotle, NEAristotleNicomachean Ethics (NE) 4.3 & 3.11). The ideological triumph of the honnêtehonnête homme homme [honorable man] was prepared by the introduction of Greek and Latin authors in the sixteenth century and by the social, political, and theological upheavals of the Wars of ReligionWars of Religion. Christian values and beliefs still dominated the early seventeenth century, and strict conformity to Christian morality and intellectual and religious dogma was enforced by the Jesuits and the Paris ParlementParlement. Feeling the need for a new ethical outlook and way of life, but one that would not disturb dogmatic opinion, educated elites of the early seventeenth century returned to the humanist res literaria [literary canon]. It allowed them to pull ideas from a range of ethical systems, including Christianity, to fashion the ethosethos of honnêtehonnête hommehonnêtetété [nobilitynobility] that responded to the changed political and social environment.3
A simple but sharp contrast between magnanimitymagnanimity and moderationvirtuemoderation emerges from a comparison of Rodrigue in Corneille’s Le Cid (1637) and Philinte in Molière’s Le Misanthrope (1666). Both these virtuevirtues of characterethoscharacter presuppose the assistance of an intellectual virtuevirtue, phronēsisphronēsis, often translated as practical wisdomphronēsispractical wisdom, or more loosely, good judgment, defined as the ability to reason correctly about means and ends (NE 4.6). Whereas phronēsisphronēsis enables Rodrigue to make correct judgments that lead to life-and-death feats of valor, it allows Philinte to make correct judgments productive of pleasure in social situations. In Le Cid (Act 1, Scene 4), Rodrigue reasons that failing to fight Dom Gomès, his fiancée’s father, will cost him both his honor and his fiancée (she will not love him disgraced), and so he fights the duel to preserve his honor, resigning himself to the enmity of his beloved. Similarly, in Act 4, Scene 3, outnumbered by the Moors invading Seville, Rodrigue has the presence of mind to lay an ambush, lulling the enemy into a false sense of security, and turning the unfavorable circumstances to his advantage. By contrast, in Le Misanthrope (Act 1, Scene 1), Philinte displays practical wisdomphronēsispractical wisdom through worldliness: he adapts himself and his discourse to his interlocutors; he censures his own reactions of dislike or displeasure; and he regards human failings with generosity of spirit. The self-effacing moderationvirtuemoderation of Philinte, in spite of his own and everyone else’s insincerity, procures a civilized pleasure for imperfect human beings engaged in conversation.
From these examples, one could extrapolate that magnanimitymagnanimity and moderationvirtuemoderation are virtuevirtues suited to distinct sociopolitical configurations. Magnanimitymagnanimity was well adapted to a Renaissance monarchypolitymonarchy dominated by a constellation of great nobles who either played an active role in affairs of state or revolted when they felt excluded from power, whereas moderationvirtuemoderation was more appropriate to an absolutist regime in which nobles no longer had a share in sovereignty and needed the methods of civility to obtain social distinction and to secure opportunities for advancement in the service of king and country. The predominance of the warrior ethosethos in the early years of the seventeenth century and the emergence and co-existence of honnêtehonnête hommehonnêtetété alongside it, before the triumph of honnêtehonnête hommehonnêtetété in the late 1660s, parallel the messy and unsteady transition of the Renaissance monarchypolitymonarchy to a more absolutist form of rule.
Malherbe’s royal odes were composed at the early stage of these important cultural and political changes, and so it is no surprise that the virtuevirtue of magnanimitymagnanimity underpins their ideological ambitions. Furthermore, the unusual circumstances of Henri IV’s accession in the late sixteenth century (the famous battles he won against LeagueLeaguer and Spanish opposition, and his remarkable trajectory from leader of the ProtestantProtestant opposition to Catholic king of France) must have contributed to the centrality of magnanimitymagnanimity in the royal odes. What is surprising and deserves a closer look, however, is the emphasis which the odes place on the monarch’s natural virtuevirtue. This is unexpected because ready-made, competing versions of monarchal sacrality were available in the late sixteenth century. LeagueLeaguers clung to the traditional image of the Most Christian King, while royalists appealed to the tenets of neo-Stoicstoicismism to represent the monarch as the embodiment of divine reason (Crouzet 90-93).
Contrary to what one might expect, moreover, СКАЧАТЬ