Digital Life. Tim Markham
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Digital Life - Tim Markham страница 10

Название: Digital Life

Автор: Tim Markham

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Кинематограф, театр

Серия:

isbn: 9781509541072

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ implications of, finding the world and its manifold objects meaningful as such.18 The business of understanding the contingency of everyday life is both elusive and important; the notion here is that it is possible for the mobility with which one moves through digital worlds to be oriented simultaneously by appearances and by a pre-reflexive registration of their flimsiness. This is similar to the ironic stance towards the other developed by Chouliaraki, as it also is to de Beauvoir’s ethics of ambiguity. And it is not so difficult as it sounds, once the requirement of conscious reflection is taken off the table.

      The subjective crisis presented by social media is commonly articulated in terms of prescribed or provoked presentations of the self coming to be mistaken for the self. Langlois thus makes the claim that the overriding objective of these mass, structured solicitations of self-documentation can only be one of appropriating and transforming the conditions of being. It is, according to her, a matter of social media practices of self-disclosure altering our perceptions not simply of who we are, but also how we can be (Langlois 2014: 122). Stiegler (1998b: 80–1) makes a comparable point when he writes of an inversion that has taken place such that contemporary digital media cultures relate the experience of life with such force that they seem not only to anticipate but to determine life itself. That word ‘force’ is doing as much work here as ‘pace’ was previously, as though it is inarguable that there has been a definitive usurping of being by the appearance of being – despite the fact that the distinction between the experience of everyday life and life itself has never been something that can be made a stable object of consciousness. Both metaphors are helpful as shorthand, but they allow the argument to run away towards a presumptuous conclusion; as does, arguably, the idea of the colonization of a space of subjectification by digital media. In all cases the realm of selfhood is imagined as something discrete, finite and originary, something that could previously be defended but is now overwhelmed by technology run amok. But if there is no natural, stable territory of subjectification upon which a critical ethics of being might be based, agility becomes a more important resource to have to-hand than resilience.

      Now, this could be taken to suggest that whatever makes digital spaces more easily navigable, more fluidly explorable, counts as meaningful knowledge of the digital – which seems the opposite of a critical perspective. But the point is to prise apart the critical and the perspectival; the former is not contingent upon the latter. In short, critical, practical knowledge of the digital, insofar as it propels wayfaring and thus meaning-making, is that which discloses the world to-hand – as always-already meaningful, navigable and useful – at the same time as it discloses that ready-to-handness itself is predicated on learned, embedded and collective practices of navigation and meaning-making. The performance of identity on social media reveals both the importance of doing it well, and the arbitrariness of its recognition as important – not in a reflective, media literate manner, but at the level of making one’s way through the platform experience. It feels like a meaningful thing to do, though it is thoroughly improvised; it feels like there is a lot at stake, and yet it is entirely provisional.

      All of which brings us back to Couldry and Hepp and the laudable attention they give to the consequences for individuals’ everyday experience of the ‘world-making strategies of governing institutions’ (2017: 163). They take issue with Bruno Latour on the question of digital traces, and in particular Latour’s insistence that these give us direct access to experience. Instead, they counter that such directness cannot be assumed since those traces are dependent on the technical architectures and processes of institutions. Looked at another way, both perspectives are correct. It is undoubtedly right that we pay heed to the commercial and programmatic structuring of digital meaning-making practices, but if we take Heidegger’s account of thrownness seriously there is nothing less real about the meaningful experiences that emerge from such practices. Further, this generative inauthenticity does not commit Heidegger – or, I would argue, any of us – to accepting the status quo unquestioningly, nor does it absolve us of the responsibility for improving the (digital) world as we find it.