Michael Walzer. J. Toby Reiner
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Michael Walzer - J. Toby Reiner страница 14

Название: Michael Walzer

Автор: J. Toby Reiner

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509526338

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ – prefer. While self-determination is a core part of Walzer’s political thought (see especially Walzer 1981), it is, as Orend notes, extremely difficult to imagine how any army intervening in a war might map out a strategy of maintaining a balance of forces rather than winning the war (Orend 2013: 90). Once battle is joined, it seems impossible to do anything but try to win. A strategy of containment would inevitably be a losing one. Walzer is of course a political theorist, not a military strategist, but if Orend’s claim is true, as seems likely, it would appear that counter-interventionists have to decide between allowing the original intervention to alter the course of the war and winning the war themselves; they simply cannot ensure local forces prevail. This is especially so because of difficulty determining to what extent forces depend on external intervention. In the Syrian civil war, for example, how can Americans determine precisely the extent to which the Assad regime relies on Russian weaponry? (On Syria, see Walzer 2018: 6–7, 71–3.)

      Walzer’s defense of pre-emption again follows the logic of maintaining international pluralism. He is at pains to distinguish pre-emption from “preventive” war, such as that later waged by the USA against Iraq in 2003 (on which, see the Preface to the fourth edition of Wars, Walzer 2006c), which he deems unjust. On Walzer’s account, preventive war responds to a threat that is somewhat distant, which means that it is freely chosen by the side waging war, even if it dubs itself the defender. By contrast, legitimate pre-emptive strikes occur when a state faces serious and imminent risks to its territorial integrity or political sovereignty. Walzer’s classic example is of the Israeli strike that launched the Six-Day War in 1967. Walzer argues that Israel was justified in pre-emptively attacking Egypt, because Egypt had deployed forces on the border and intended to place Israel in danger by doing so (Walzer 2015a: 80–5). Egypt did not accept Israel’s right to exist, so Walzer endorses Abba Eban’s suggestion that the destruction of an independent state be named the crime of “policide” in international law (52).

      Yet the crucial issue in assessing Walzer’s argument on pre-emption is not his intention but, rather, how it conforms to his theory. I think we must come to a mixed conclusion. By Walzer’s admission, the argument marks “a major revision of the legalist paradigm” because it means that war can occur without an “immediate intention to launch such an attack” (Walzer 2015a: 84). This makes the argument seem inconsistent with Walzer’s insistence that just-war theory base itself on the war convention. However, Walzer’s adherence to the convention is not uncritical: he holds that its judgments must form the starting point for thinking about war, but not the conclusion. That is why exceptions that are in keeping with its spirit are warranted. Here Walzer is on somewhat solid ground, for he notes that if Israel could do nothing to resist Egypt mobilizing on its borders, then Israel would have been vulnerable to attack at any time, and its territorial integrity permanently eroded (83). It does seem intolerable to anyone committed to the survival of a system of independent states that a state should have to tolerate the permanent massing of hostile troops on its borders, and so that some sort of Israeli action must be considered justifiable. On the other hand, that does not mean that any Israeli gambit would be legitimate, nor that the Israeli attack that all-but-destroyed the Egyptian air force necessarily was. Israel might have followed the prescription Walzer would, decades later, suggest the US adopt with regard to Saddam Hussein’s Iraq: a “small war” consisting of enforcement of a no-fly zone someway from the border, with threats to attack if the no-fly zone were not respected (Walzer 2006c). One of the important developments in the theory of just war since 1977 relates to jus ad vim, or when it is legitimate to use force short of full-scale war. As a general principle, nations invoking Walzer’s doctrine of pre-emption would enhance their legitimacy were they to do their utmost to ensure use of the minimum force required as a gesture toward their defensive purposes.

      The issue revolves around two competing approaches to military ethics. The emerging orthodoxy in the field is cosmopolitan: it seeks to rethink just wars as rights-protection on a global scale by establishing a world order comprised of “legitimate states” that are “minimally just” because they do their utmost to protect the human rights of their constituents (Orend 2013: 35–43). Thus, David Luban argues that just wars are not fought in defense of the sovereignty of states but of “socially basic human rights” (Luban 1980a: 175; see Shue 1980 for an account of basic rights). Cosmopolitan just-war theorists tend to criticize Walzer for using the legalist paradigm, which grants states’ rights to non-interference by analogy with СКАЧАТЬ