Название: Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science: A History (Third Edition)
Автор: Thomas J. Hickey
Издательство: Ingram
Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты
isbn: 9780692650738
isbn:
If the conclusions agree with the laws within the degree of approximation corresponding to the measurements taken in the experiments, then the theory is said to be an acceptable theory. Such acceptable theory may in turn be used for the further development of measuring instruments used in experiments, as well as constituting the final product of the scientific endeavor with its maximum economy. Improved theory produces improved instruments, which in turn produce better measurements. These better measurements reduce the range of the indeterminacy in the numerical data, which may cause the theories to fail in their predictions. Such failure will occasion two types of responses. The initial response is to modify the theory with corrections, which will enable the predictions made with the theory to fall within the smaller range of indeterminacy produced with improved measurements. But these corrections also complicate the theory, and in due course “good sense” may lead some physicists to decide to refrain from adding more complicating corrections, and instead attempt to revise the hypothetical postulates of the symbolic schema, i.e., of the whole theory itself. The accomplishment of such a revision is the work of the genius.
But Duhem does not subscribe to the heroic concept of invention; history creates the genius as much as the genius creates history. The physicist does not choose the hypotheses on which he will build a new theory; the theory germinates within him. This germination is not sufficiently explained by the contemplation of the experimental laws that the theory must represent. It is a larger cultural development. In due course when the cultural process that he calls universal science has prepared minds sufficiently to receive a new theory, it arises in a nearly inevitable manner. Often physicists who do not know one another and who are working great distances from one another, generate the same theory at the same time. In the course of his studies the historian of science according to Duhem often observes this simultaneous emergence of the same theory in countries far from one another.
Scientific Explanation
On Duhem’s philosophy theories do not explain the laws nor do the laws explain the facts. Explanation is proper only to metaphysics and not to science. In the opening sentence of the introduction to his Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, Duhem says that he offers a simple logical analysis of the method by which physical science makes progress. While affirming the autonomy of physics with his thesis that agreement with experiment is the sole criterion of truth for a physical theory, Duhem has a distinctive concept of scientific progress, which he elaborates in the appendices to the book.
He says that there are two types of development in physics that are occurring simultaneously. One is what today would be called the revolutionary type of development consisting of a succession of alternative theories, in which one theory arises, dominates the scene for the moment, and then collapses to be replaced by another theory. The other is an evolutionary progress in which more ample and more precise mathematical representation of the phenomenal world is constantly disclosed by experiment. When the progress of experimental science goes counter to a theory and compels the theory to be modified or transformed, the purely representative part enters nearly whole into the new theory, bringing to it the inheritance of all the valuable possessions of the old theory, while the hypothetical part falls away in order to give way to another theory. The first type is identified with the mechanistic physical systems including Newtonian physics as well as Cartesian and atomic physics. The second type is identified with general thermodynamics, which Duhem believes will lead physical theory toward its goal.
Duhem believes that the goal of physics is the convergence toward an analogy with Aristotle’s physics. He concludes in his discussion of the value of theory, that the physicist is compelled to recognize that it would be unreasonable to work for the progress of physical theory, if theory were not the increasingly better defined and more precise reflection of a metaphysics. He thus concludes his book with the thesis that belief in an order transcending physics is the ultimate metaphysical justification of physical theory.
Duhem’s History of Physics
Just as Mach had written a history of physics viewed through the lenses of his philosophy of science, so too did Duhem. However, Duhem’s effort was relatively monumental; it is a work originally intended to be twelve volumes of which ten were actually written before its author’s death in September 1916. This magnum opus was his System of the World: A History of Cosmological Doctrines from Plato to Copernicus. The central thesis of this work is summarized in a much smaller book begun earlier, To Save the Phenomena: An Essay on the Idea of Physical Theory from Plato to Galileo (1908). His thesis is that the hypotheses of physics and especially the heliocentric hypothesis in astronomy are mere mathematical contrivances for the purpose of “saving the phenomena”.
Pope Urban VIII condemned Galileo in 1633 for maintaining that Copernicus’ heliocentric theory is not merely a mathematical contrivance, but is rather a description of the real world. Formerly known as Cardinal Bellarmine, this Pope maintained that regardless of how numerous and exact may be the confirmations of a theory by experience, these confirmations can never transform a hypothesis into a certain truth that can be taken realistically, since this transformation would require that the experimental facts should contradict any other hypotheses that might be conceived, a requirement that cannot logically be satisfied. Galileo, on the other hand, maintained that because Copernicus’s theory saved the phenomena more adequately than any alternative hypothesis, the Copernican theory had to be a realistic one.
Contemporary pragmatists agree with Duhem’s rejection of any prior ontological criteria for the criticism of scientific theory, but contrary to Duhem they furthermore agree with Galileo’s practice of ontological relativity, i.e., scientific realism. Contemporary pragmatists are realists, who let the most empirically adequate theory decide the ontology. Galileo’s argument for realism is the same as Quine’s doctrine of ontological relativity, and Feyerabend calls it the Galileo-Einstein tradition of realism. And Heisenberg invoked this tradition, when he referenced Einstein’s realistic interpretation of relativistic time in the relativity theory, and then used it as a precedent for his own realistic interpretation of the quantum theory’s duality thesis, notwithstanding Bohr’s instrumentalist complementarity principle. Duhem, however, denied that theory is realistic, and he construed Galileo’s argument as a case of the fallacy of the crucial experiment; he argued that it is impossible to enunciate all the possible hypotheses, and establish the truth of one by elimination of all others. The accomplishment that Duhem credits to Kepler and Galileo is the rejection of Aristotle’s view that celestial and terrestrial physics are fundamentally different, and that hypotheses of physics must save all the phenomena of the inanimate world.
The New Physics vs. the Old Philosophy
The history of philosophy of science has been greatly influenced by the history of physics. As twentieth-century physicists found themselves departing farther and farther from Newtonian physics, they also found themselves departing farther and farther from the positivist philosophy notwithstanding the positivists’ criticisms of Newtonian physics. At the beginning of the century positivism was not merely the academic philosophy it later became. It was for a time the working philosophy for many physicists including those who produced the revolutionary relativity and quantum theories. It achieved ascendancy in academia during the first half of the century, where it evolved into logical positivism with the introduction of the symbolic logic, which made it irrelevant to the practice of basic research in the sciences. But long before academia recognized positivism as a kind СКАЧАТЬ