Название: The Wiley Handbook of Sustainability in Higher Education Learning and Teaching
Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Жанр: Прочая образовательная литература
isbn: 9781119852834
isbn:
Thus, pro‐environmental behavior sourced from good character and framed by the pleasure of acting from the internal source of character rather than from an externally imposed obligation and sacrifice might make a difference in terms of efficacy (Treanor 2014). As a result, virtue ethics may contribute to the much‐needed societal coordination for sustainability problems inasmuch as it is one of the most agreed upon ethical frameworks, both historically and cross‐culturally (Peterson and Seligman 2004; Crossan et al. 2013). The ideas of virtue and vice have been consistently used along history to express stable states of character that reflect praiseworthy or blameworthy behaviors, and that include perception, emotion, desire, deliberation, and action (Kristjánsson 2013). Consequently, this perspective could be easily accepted in a coordinated multistakeholder approach to the management of sustainability problems.
4.3.2 Virtues Are Relational
Virtues and the virtuous person are not self‐generated, but are developed in relationship with the agent's communities (see Sanderse 2012). More specifically, virtues are relational because they are created by the community, from a specific cultural value and set of frames of reference virtues are learned and displayed in the community, through the interactions with our environments; and virtues are intended for the community, insomuch as personal flourishing is regarded as a collective task. Aristotle considered that a flourishing life is understood only as a shared life in the polis and can be realized only in a well‐governed community (NE 1094b). Thus, a good life would be part of the general discipline of politics (Kristjánsson 2013, 2016).
As noted, ill‐defined socioecological problems require collective work to map, identify, and reconcile values and goals behind action (Blok et al. 2016). Virtues, as the expression of collective flourishing, can provide a general compass for that collective work. The relational nature of virtues would emphasize agents' commitment to and responsibility toward the flourishing of the community rather than their rights in the community (Dobson 2003). Therefore, virtues would provide an effective moral and political grounding to ES and its focus on cultivating citizenship for sustainability.
4.3.3 Virtues Are Situational
A virtuous character includes values (with social flourishing as a compass) and the disposition to act on them in a stable way. Thus, even though virtue ethics emphasizes the agent's whole moral inner life rather than the rightness of their isolated actions, virtues can also be interpreted as inspiring principles or creating general prescriptions to act, i.e. doing what is honest, generous, just; or not doing what is dishonest, mean, unjust (Hursthouse 1999; Hartman 2006). However, the application of those general prescriptions is dependent on time, place, and culture (Sanderse 2012; Russell 2015), i.e. the agent requires the ability to perceive, sense, and deliberate how to act from virtue in each particular situation (Hartman 2006), as clearly illustrated by Yearley (1990, p. 14): “I do not act benevolently in order to be benevolent (…). I act benevolently because the situation I face fits a description of a situation that elicits my benevolence.” Therefore, virtues provide the appropriate reasons and emotions to decide what to do in each situation we face (and why). This is especially convenient for contexts marked by complexity, novelty, rapid change, and uncertainty, as socioecological challenges are. In these situations, a predefined set of rules or a focus on the (unforeseeable) consequences of behaviors may be a doubtful foundation for knowing how to act.
The variety of skills needed to act virtuously across very different situations involves all kinds of virtues at play. However, Aristotle conceives virtues as interrelated and interdependent (Jacobs 2017) through one virtue: the virtue of practical wisdom or phronesis. Understood as a meta‐virtue, since no other virtue can be exercised without it (Hursthouse 1999), phronesis can be defined as “the knowledge of which acts are virtuous in which situations” (Curzer 2012, p. 12). Aristotle highlights that, unlike scientific or theoretical knowledge, practical wisdom “is concerned with human affairs and what can be deliberated about (…). Nor is practical wisdom knowledge of universals only. On the contrary, it must also know particulars. For it is practical, and action is concerned with particulars” (NE 1141b).
Since phronesis is so central to virtuous choice, it deserves special attention when it comes to the ES of virtue, as we will develop in Section 4.4.
4.3.4 Virtues Are Learnable (and Teachable)
Aristotle distinguishes natural virtue from full virtue (NE 1144b). While we may have an innate disposition for justice, courage, compassion, or generosity, for instance, we need to develop understanding for those dispositions to be fully just, courageous, compassionate, or generous. In other words, it is because we learn to become fully virtuous that makes the virtuous acts actually virtuous (Curzer 2012, p. 12). For Aristotle, full virtue and practical wisdom are strongly intertwined, since “it is neither possible to be fully good without practical wisdom nor practically wise without virtue of character” (NE 1145a).
This means that we have to learn how to turn our natural receptivity to virtues into full virtues. We grow into virtues through habituation, and virtues require practice, in a similar way to acquiring skills, e.g. we evolve as a generous person by performing generous actions, as we become pianists by playing the piano (NE 1103a). But acquiring both virtues and skills is not a passive process; both need effort, focus, and the right kind of practice (Russell 2015). Nevertheless, there is a difference between acquiring skills and acquiring virtues: unlike skills, virtues are essential for flourishing, and their scope and depth for human life are broader (Kristjánsson 2013). Thus, it is not only the amount of practice that matters, but rather the way the agent understands and carries on that practice. Aristotle is adamant: “It makes a huge [difference], or rather, all the difference” (NE 1103b). So eudaimonia as collective human flourishing or true happiness for the common good would be the lodestar guiding the acquisition of virtue, and arguably also guiding ES projects. In this sense, Kristjansson (2016) concludes from his review on flourishing as an overarching aim of education (p. 18):
The uniqueness of a flourishing paradigm on human well‐being lies in its insistence that education and teaching is woven into the very fabric of flourishing – as work in progress until our dying day – and that any effort deserving of the name “education” must be characterised as education for flourishing.
It follows from the above reasons that the practice of cultivating virtues requires guidance. This guidance goes well beyond mechanically imitating the acts performed by virtuous exemplars, but focusing on the qualities that make a person virtuous, allowing students to choose their particular perspective aimed at developing the right criteria to become so (Athanassoulis 2018). That perspective can only be understood from within (Sherman 1989, p. 418). Again, phronesis lies at the heart of the qualities that make a person virtuous, manifested in the ability “to see” what is required in each situation to arrive at a virtuous decision (Waddock 2010; Russell 2015).
СКАЧАТЬ