Deliberative Democracy. Ian O'Flynn
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Deliberative Democracy - Ian O'Flynn страница 7

Название: Deliberative Democracy

Автор: Ian O'Flynn

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781509523498

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ arena? Even if it were possible for large numbers of people to gather together, the inevitable time constraints under which political decisions usually need to be made would surely make it impossible for everyone to speak.

      Empirical research is particularly good at pointing out problems of this sort – in this case, the practical difficulty of reconciling values of deliberation and mass participation. The point is not that there are no solutions to problems of this sort – research into online deliberation, for example, suggests some intriguing answers (see, e.g., Neblo et al. 2018). Rather, the point is that empirical research can compel us to think harder about our normative commitments. At the same time, however, Thompson insists that, while empirical research may ‘pose some challenging questions, and even offer some provocative answers … it does not have the last word’ (2008, 513). On the contrary, if democratic values stand in conflict, ‘we still have to decide under what conditions which value should have priority, and which combination of the values is optimal. That decision depends partly on considerations that are not primarily empirical’ (2008, 513; cf. Graham Smith 2011, 898). In other words, decisions about how to reconcile conflicting values such as deliberation and participation are never just practical or pragmatic, but inevitably bring larger normative questions and concerns into play.

      Granted, abstraction plays a crucial role in (among other things) clarifying and differentiating concepts, which in turn is crucial to theory building. But on the whole, it is probably fair to say that deliberative democrats have eschewed highly abstract thinking. They typically assume that theories of deliberative democracy should take account of the normal circumstances of political life and they have sought to develop their accounts accordingly (see Rawls 2001, 4; cf. Mutz 2008). In fact, if anything, they may have been too attentive to those circumstances: in an effort to develop the concept in ways that demonstrate its practical relevance, some deliberative democrats may be guilty of concept stretching (Goodin 2018; Steiner 2008). Take, for instance, the goal of reaching an agreed judgement or consensus – people agreeing both on a course of action and on the reasons for it. For some, this notion sits uncomfortably with respect for social pluralism or diversity. Instead of consensus, we should instead aim for ‘workable agreements’ in which people agree on a course of action but for different reasons (Dryzek 2000, 170; Curato et al. 2017, 31). However, if workable agreement is made the goal, then ‘it is unclear what purpose is served by telling one another our reasons at all’ (Goodin 2018, 31; see also Neblo 2015, 106).

      There are many reasons to trace the origins of contemporary ideas about deliberative democracy. Of those reasons, one of the more interesting is that it shows us how deliberation, political equality and accountability came to be so central to democratic theory.

      Theorists of deliberative democracy are wont to trace its origins back to ancient Athens (e.g., Fishkin 2018, 51–4). This tendency is perhaps understandable. As Josiah Ober explains, the ‘history of Athenian popular government shows that making good use of dispersed knowledge is the original source of democracy’s strength’ (2008, 2). The most famous institution in this respect was the Assembly (or ekklēsia) in which each citizen had the right to participate. However, because large public gatherings are not effective instruments of government, the Athenian system also relied on a 500-member governing Council (or boulē), chosen by lot from among those citizens who wished to volunteer to serve for a fixed term. Importantly, the council was charged not just with the day-to-day running of the state, but with setting the assembly’s agenda and evaluating proposals before resubmitting them to the assembly for decision (see also Schwartzberg 2015).

      Thus, as Daniela Cammack concludes, the ‘distinctive feature of Athenian democracy was that citizens gathered in large numbers to decide actions by the result of votes, not that they took part in discussions or debates on a grand scale’ (2021, 162–3). In other words, the principal means of organizing dispersed knowledge was aggregation, not deliberation (cf. Ober 2008, 27, 98). In response, one could argue that, while ancient Athens was not quite the deliberative epitome it is sometimes taken to be, what ultimately matters is not historical accuracy but the normative ideas it suggests. That would be fine were it not for the fact that Athenian institutions were far from inclusive. They were, in fact, highly exclusive. Women, foreign residents and slaves – on most estimates, well more than half of the adult population – were not permitted to participate in political life and certainly not in the Assembly (Weale 2018, 18–23). Upper-class women could not leave the house unless they were veiled and accompanied by a male relative, while there is a good case for arguing that slavery was the essential condition for civic liberty: without it, the freedom and (just as importantly) the time to participate in the Assembly and to volunteer for the Council may simply not have existed.

      The upshot is that, while Athenian institutions may have been designed for organizing the dispersed knowledge of citizens, the Assembly and Council were principally aggregative institutions and citizenship itself was narrowly circumscribed. There is, admittedly, a case for saying that since every democracy is a creature of its time, it should be evaluated on its own terms. But there is a stronger case for saying that the history of democracy is a history of inclusion. Today, we (rightly) tend to ask not just if there is political equality but also how far that equality extends (Dahl 1989, 88).