The Philosopher's Toolkit. Julian Baggini
Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Philosopher's Toolkit - Julian Baggini страница 17

Название: The Philosopher's Toolkit

Автор: Julian Baggini

Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited

Жанр: Афоризмы и цитаты

Серия:

isbn: 9781119103233

isbn:

СКАЧАТЬ R. Berger (1977). Studying Deductive Logic

       S.K. Langer (2011). ‘Truth and validity'. In: Introduction to Symbolic Logic, 3rd edn, Ch. 1, pp. 182–90

       * Jc Beall and Shay Allen Logan (2017). Logic: The Basics, 2nd edn

      Given the definition of a valid argument, it may seem obvious what an invalid one looks like. Certainly, it’s simple enough to define an invalid argument: it is an argument where the truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion. To put it another way, if the premises of an invalid argument are true, the conclusion may still be false. Invalid arguments are unsuccessful deductions and therefore, in a sense, are not truly deductions at all.

      To be armed with an adequate definition of invalidity, however, may not be enough to enable you to make use of this tool. The man who went looking for a horse equipped only with the definition ‘solid‐hoofed, herbivorous, domesticated mammal used for draught work and riding’ (Collins English Dictionary) discovered as much, to his cost. In addition to the definition, you need to understand the definition’s full import. Consider this argument:

      1 Vegetarians do not eat pork sausages.

      2 Gandhi did not eat pork sausages.

      3 Therefore, Gandhi was a vegetarian.

      If you’re thinking carefully, you’ll have probably noticed that this is an invalid argument. But it wouldn’t be surprising if you and a fair number of readers required a double take to see that it is in fact invalid. Now, this is a clear case, and if a capable intellect can easily miss a clear case of invalidity in the midst of an article devoted to a careful explanation of the concept, imagine how easy it is not to spot invalid arguments more generally.

      So, the fact that Gandhi did not eat pork sausages does not, in conjunction with the first premise, guarantee that he was a vegetarian. It just so happens that he was. But, of course, since an argument can only be sound if it’s valid, the fact that all three of the propositions it asserts are true does not make it a sound argument.

      Remember that validity is a property of an argument’s structure of form. In this case, the form is:

      1 All Xs are Ys.

      2 Z is a Y.

      3 Therefore, Z is an X.

      Here X is substituted for ‘vegetarian’, Y for ‘person who does not eat pork sausages’, and Z for ‘Gandhi’. We can see why this structure is invalid by replacing these variables with other terms that produce true premises but a clearly false conclusion. (Replacing terms creates what logicians call a new ‘substitution instance’ of the argument form.) If we substitute ‘cat’ for X, ‘meat eater’ for Y, and ‘the president of the United States’ for Z, we get:

      1 All cats are meat eaters.

      2 The president of the United States is a meat eater.

      3 Therefore, the president of the United States is a cat.

      The premises are true, but the conclusion clearly false. This cannot therefore be a valid argument structure. (Showing that an argument form is invalid by making substitutions that result in true premises but a false conclusion is called showing invalidity by ‘counterexample’. It’s a powerful skill well worth cultivating. See 1.7 and 3.12.)

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.2 Deduction

      2 1.4 Validity and soundness

      3 1.7 Fallacies

      READING

       * Irving M. Copi (2010). Introduction to Logic, 14th edn

       * Harry Gensler (2016). Introduction to Logic, 3rd edn

       * Patrick J. Hurley and Lori Watson (2017). A Concise Introduction to Logic, 13th edn

      Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803–82) may have written in his well‐known 1841 essay, ‘Self‐reliance’, that ‘a foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds’, but of all the philosophical crimes there are, the one with which you really don’t want to get charged is inconsistency. For most purposes it’s not too much to say that consistency is the cornerstone of rationality. To do philosophy well, therefore, it’s crucial to master the idea and the practice of consistency.

      Statements are contradictory when they are opposite in ‘truth value’: when one is true the other is false, and vice versa. Statements are contrary when they can’t both be true but, unlike contradictories, can both be false. With contraries, at least one is false.

      Consistency, like contradiction and contrariety, are about comparing two or more different statements. A single sentence can, however, be self‐contradictory when it makes an assertion that is necessarily false – often by conjoining two inconsistent sentences, such as p and not‐p (1.12). You might call such a sentence self‐inconsistent. (Compare this with the idea of the paraconsistent in 3.10.)

      All this can be boiled down to a simple formulation: two or more statements are consistent when it’s logically possible for them all to be true (a) in the same sense and (b) at the same time. Two or more statements are inconsistent when it is not possible for them all to be true in the same sense and at the same time.

СКАЧАТЬ